Notes

Chapter 10: Processes of Perception and Analysis

Section 3: Defining the Notion of Randomness


History [of randomness definitions]

Randomness and unpredictability were discussed as general notions in antiquity in connection both with questions of free will (see page 1135) and games of chance. When probability theory emerged in the mid-1600s it implicitly assumed sequences random in the sense of having limiting frequencies following its predictions. By the 1800s there was extensive debate about this, but in the early 1900s with the advent of statistical mechanics and measure theory the use of ensembles (see page 1020) turned discussions of probability away from issues of randomness in individual sequences. With the development of statistical hypothesis testing in the early 1900s various tests for randomness were proposed (see page 1084). Sometimes these were claimed to have some kind of general significance, but mostly they were just viewed as simple practical methods. In many fields outside of statistics, however, the idea persisted even to the 1990s that block frequencies (or flat frequency spectra) were somehow the only ultimate tests for randomness. In 1909 Emile Borel had formulated the notion of normal numbers (see page 912) whose infinite digit sequences contain all blocks with equal frequency. And in the 1920s Richard von Mises—attempting to capture the observed lack of systematically successful gambling schemes—suggested that randomness for individual infinite sequences could be defined in general by requiring that "collectives" consisting of elements appearing at positions specified by any procedure should show equal frequencies. To disallow procedures say specially set up to pick out all the infinite number of 1's in a sequence Alonzo Church in 1940 suggested that only procedures corresponding to finite computations be considered. (Compare page 1021 on coarse-graining in thermodynamics.) Starting in the late 1940s the development of information theory began to suggest connections between randomness and inability to compress data, but emphasis on p Log[p] measures of information content (see page 1071) reinforced the idea that block frequencies are the only real criterion for randomness. In the early 1960s, however, the notion of algorithmic randomness (see note above) was introduced by Gregory Chaitin, Andrei Kolmogorov and Ray Solomonoff. And unlike earlier proposals the consequences of this definition seemed to show remarkable consistency (in 1966 for example Per Martin-Löf proved that in effect it covered all possible statistical tests)—so that by the early 1990s it had become generally accepted as the appropriate ultimate definition of randomness. In the 1980s, however, work on cryptography had led to the study of some slightly weaker definitions of randomness based on inability to do cryptanalysis or make predictions with polynomial-time computations (see page 1089). But quite what the relationship of any of these definitions might be to natural science or everyday experience was never much discussed. Note that definitions of randomness given in dictionaries tend to emphasize lack of aim or purpose, in effect following the common legal approach of looking at underlying intentions (or say at physical construction of dice) rather than trying to tell if things are random from their observed behavior.



Image Source Notebooks:

From Stephen Wolfram: A New Kind of Science [citation]